I have discovered that a large proportion of highly intelligent, mathematically
sophisticated, researchers have had no personal experience of finding
geometrical constructions and proofs, which used to be a standard feature of
mathematical education in schools until around the middle of the 20th century,
when such teaching was replaced by an emphasis on use of formal, rigorous,
logic-based reasoning and set theory, as recommended by the Bourbaki movement.
See
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Nicolas_Bourbaki
https://www.encyclopedia.com/science/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/bourbaki-school-mathematics
As a result, there are now many highly intelligent, well educated researchers in many disciplines, including mathematics, psychology, neuroscience, philosophy and AI, who have never encountered mathematical applications of ancient forms of spatial reasoning that used to be a standard part of mathematical education, and which cannot be replicated using standard AI mechanisms based solely on digital computation, and therefore do not allow mechanisms in which shapes, sizes, angles, and relative distances are continuously transformed.
Moreover, those ancient forms of mathematical discovery cannot be based on "Neural network" (NN) mechanisms that function by collecting statistical evidence and then deriving probabilities, whose influence can be propagated across links in neural networks. Such NN mechanisms can never be used to prove that something is necessarily true or necessarily false (impossible) because necessity and impossibility cannot be derived from statistical data: only probability (probable truth or probable falsehood) can be derived.
Yet, ancient mathematicians used geometric reasoning to establish impossibility or necessity, for example that the internal angles of a planar triangle necessarily sum to 180 degrees (a straight line); and Pythagoras' theorem: if squares are constructed on the sides of a right-angled planar triangle then the area of the square on the hypotenuse (the longest side) is necessarily equal to the sum of the areas of the squares on the other two sides of the triangle.
I am not the only person who regards the failure to teach the ancient spatial,
or diagrammatic, modes of reasoning as an educationally disastrous mistake. For
example, Benoit Mandelbrot, who made major contributions to the study of fractal
geometry, shared that opinion. For information about fractals see:
https://www.ibm.com/ibm/history/ibm100/us/en/icons/fractal/.
Last updated:
10 Oct 2022 (modified note on mathematical education above)
2 May 2020 then 22 Aug 2022 (minor re-organisation and re-formatting)
26 May 2019 (minor re-formatting).
5 Apr 2018: Earlier version of Pardoe proof by Thibaut (1809)
referenced below.
25 Apr 2016; 8 Sep 2017; 23 Sep 2017;
26 Feb 2015: added link to document showing how in P-geometry
an arbitrary angle can be trisected (impossible in pure Euclidean geometry):
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/trisect.html
29 May 2013
....Updates: part of the original file deleted...
This file is
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/triangle-sum.html
PDF derivative:
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/triangle-sum.pdf
As we'll see below, that suggests a way of proving the theorem by considering a succession of rotations and noticing what they add up to, an idea suggested to me many years ago by a former student, Mary Pardoe, after she had become a mathematics teacher.
One of the standard ways of proving the following theorem is presented below:
Triangle Sum Theorem (TST):
The interior angles of a triangle add up to a straight line, or half a rotation (180 degrees).
The standard methods of proof all make use of some version of Euclid's parallel postulate, (Axiom 5 in Euclid's elements) which can be formulated in several equivalent ways, e.g.
Definition:
Two straight lines L1 and L2 are parallel if and only if they are co-planar and have no point in common, no matter how far they are extended.Postulate:
Given a straight line L in a plane, and a point P in the plane not on L, there is exactly one line through P that is in the plane and parallel to L. (That was not Euclid's formulation, but is perhaps intuitively the clearest formulation.)
All of this presupposes the concept of "straightness" of a line. For now I'll
take that concept for granted, without attempting to define it, though we can
note that if a line is straight it is also symmetric about itself (it coincides
with its reflection) and also it can be slid along itself without any gaps
appearing. If it were possible to view a straight line from one end it would
appear as a point, in an environment in which light is not "bent" by a
strong gravitational field, or a change in the material through which it passes.
[I am glossing over a number of problems about definability of geometrical
properties of lines, surfaces, etc.]
The "standard" ways of proving the Triangle Sum Theorem
make use of properties of angles formed
when a straight line joins or crosses a pair of parallel lines. E,g,
COR: Corresponding angles are equal:BACK TO CONTENTS
If two lines L1, L2 are parallel and a third line L3 is drawn from any point P1 on L1 to a point P2 on L2 and continued beyond P2,
then the angle that L1 makes with the line L3 at point P1, and the angle L2 makes with the line L3 at point P2 (where the angles are on the same side of both lines) are equal.ALT: Alternate angles are equal:
If two lines L1, L2 are parallel and a third line L3 is drawn from any point P1
on L1 to a point P2 on L2,
then the angle L1 makes with the line L3 at point P1, and the angle L2 makes
with the line L3 at point P2 (on the opposite sides of both lines) are equal.For more on transversals and relations between the angles they create, see
http://www.mathsisfun.com/geometry/parallel-lines.html
That page teaches concepts with some interactive illustrations, but presents no proofs.Standard Euclidean proofs of COR and ALT are presented here:
https://proofwiki.org/wiki/Parallelism_implies_Equal_Corresponding_Angles
https://proofwiki.org/wiki/Parallelism_implies_Equal_Alternate_Interior_Angles
Figure Ang1:
Warning: I have found some online proofs of theorems in Euclidean geometry with bugs apparently due to carelessness, so it is important to check every such proof found online. The fact that individual thinkers can check such a proof is in part of what needs to be explained.
Note: In the original publication reporting this proof I mistakenly referred to the author as Mary Ensor, her name as a student. I think she was already Mary Pardoe at the time she visited me.
Her proof just involves rotating a single directed line segment (or arrow, or pencil, or ...) through each of the angles in turn at the corners of the triangle, which must result in its ending up in its initial location pointing in the opposite direction, without ever crossing over its original orientation.
So the total rotation angle is equivalent to a straight line, or half rotation, i.e. 180 degrees, using the convention that a full rotation is 360 degrees.
The proof is illustrated below in Figure Ang2.
In order to understand the proof, think of the blue arrow, labelled "1", as starting on line AC, pointing from A to C, and then being rotated counter-clockwise, first around point A, then around point B, then around point C until it ends up on the original line but pointing in the direction of the dark grey arrow, labelled "4".
So, understanding the proof involves considering what happens if
A "time-lapse" presentation of the proof may be clearer, as shown in Figure Ang3 (which may not work on all operating systems).
It is best to think of the proof not as a static diagram but as a process, with stages represented from left to right in Figure Ang3. In the first stage, the pale blue arrow starts on the bottom side of the triangle, pointing to the right then is rotated through each of the internal angles A, B, C, always rotated in the same direction (counter-clockwise in this case), so that it lies on each of the other sides in succession, until it is finally rotated through the third angle, c, after which it lies on the original side of the triangle, but obviously pointing in the opposite direction. Some people may prefer to rotate something like a pencil rather than imagining a rotation depicted by snapshots.
In this triangle the sides are not very different in length, which conceals a problem that can arise if the first side the arrow is on is very short and the other two are much longer. If the length of the rotating arrow is fixed by the length of the first side, you would need to imagine either that the arrow stretches or shrinks as it rotates, or that it slides along a line after reaching it so as to be able to rotate around the next vertex. Alternatively you can imagine that the depicted arrow is part of a much longer invisible arrow, so that, as the invisible arrow rotates from one side to another, it always extends beyond both ends of the new side, and can then rotate around the next vertex. I leave it to the reader to think about these alternatives and what difference they make to the proof, and to the cognitive competences required to construct and understand the proof.
For an arrow to be rotated in a plane and end up lying in its original position it must have been rotated through some number of half-rotations. (Each half rotation brings it back to the original orientation, but pointing in alternate directions.)
Since (1) the arrow at no point crossed over its original orientation, and (2) it ended up pointing in the opposite direction to its original orientation, the total rotation was through a half circle -- which is clear if you actually perform the rotations using a physical object, such as a pencil.
And since that rotation was made up of combined rotations through angles A, B, and C, those three angles must add up to a half circle, i.e. 180 degrees.
A crucial feature of our ability to think about the diagram and the process, is that we (presumably including you, the reader) can see that the key features of the process could have been replicated, no matter what the size or orientation of the triangle, no matter what the lengths of the sides or the sizes of the angles, no matter which side the arrow starts on, no matter which way it is pointing initially, and no matter in which order the rotations are performed, e.g. A then B then C, or C reversed, then B reversed, then A reversed.
This proof of the triangle sum theorem, using a rotating moving arrow, works for all possible triangles on a plane -- as do the standard Euclidean proofs using parallel lines.
This proof is unlike standard proofs in Euclidean geometry since it involves consideration of continuous processes, and therefore involves time and temporal ordering, whereas Euclidean geometry does not explicitly mention time or properties of processes -- though there are some theorems about the locus of point or line satisfying certain constraints, which can be interpreted either as specifying properties of processes extended in time, or as properties of static trajectories, e.g. properties of lines or curves.
NOTE:
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/p-geometry.htmlNOTE (Added 8 Sep 2017):
presents a more detailed, but still incomplete, discussion, of the geometrical prerequisites for some of the above reasoning. It introduces the idea of P-geometry, which is intended to be Euclidean geometry without the Axiom of Parallels (Euclid's Axiom 5), but with time and motion added, including translation and rotation of rigid line-segments.
Aaron Sloman, 2008,The presentations produced no responses -- either critical or approving, except that in one informal discussion a mathematician objected that the proof was unacceptable because the surface of a sphere would provide a counter example. However, the surface of a sphere provides no more and no less of a problem for Pardoe's proof than for the standard Euclidean proofs since both proofs are restricted to planar surfaces.
Kantian Philosophy of Mathematics and Young Robots, in Intelligent Computer Mathematics, Eds. Autexier, S., Campbell, J., Rubio, J., Sorge, V., Suzuki, M., and Wiedijk, F., LLNCS no 5144, pp. 558-573, Springer,
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cosy/papers#tr0802
(This paper referred to Mary Ensor.)Aaron Sloman, 2010,
If learning maths requires a teacher, where did the first teachers come from?, In Proceedings Symposium on Mathematical Practice and Cognition, AISB 2010 Convention, De Montfort University, Leicester
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/10.html#1001And in talks on mathematical cognition and philosophy of mathematics here: http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/talks/
I tried searching for online proofs to see if anyone else had discovered this proof
or used it, but nothing turned up. The proof using rotation is so simple and so
effective that both Mary Pardoe and I feel sure it must have been discovered
previously.
(Added 19 Oct 2018:
It was discovered previously! See the note about Thibaut below.)
Andrea Asperti, Proof, Message and Certificate,And in this slide presentation with the same title, starting with Mary's proof, and comments on the proof by Dana Scott and Arnon Avron:
in AISC/MKM/Calculemus, 2012, pp. 17--31,
Online: http://www.cs.unibo.it/~asperti/PAPERS/proofs.pdf
http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-31374-5_2
http://www.cs.unibo.it/~asperti/SLIDES/message.pdfDana Scott commented:
"The proof is fine and really is the same as the classical proof. To see this, translate (by parallel translation) all the three angles of the triangle up to the line through the top vertex of the triangle parallel to the lower side."
"I should have commented in my explanation of the proof that if you translate the line on which the base of the triangle sits along each of the sides up to the vertex, then both actions result in the same line - the unique parallel."
Arnon Avron wrote:
If this "proof" is taught to students as a full, valid proof, then I do not see how the teacher will be able to explain to those students where the hell Euclid's fifth postulate (or the parallels axiom) is used here, or even what is the connection between the theorem and parallel lines.
I suspect we shall not have good answers to these questions until we have a much deeper understanding of the combination of biological geometric reasoning mechanisms produced by evolution plus the (epigenetic) processes of individual development leading up to use of those mechanisms -- deep enough to build a baby robot that can grow up to have the competences of ancient mathematicians.
We must not forget that however those competences are eventually explained they were of tremendous importance for human beings, not least because the contents of Euclid's Elements are still in use by engineers, scientists and mathematicians all around the planet, every day.
In particular, it is clear that all the axioms and postulates of Euclid's Elements were originally discoveries not arbitrarily selected starting points for chains of reasoning, even if Euclid can be interpreted as presenting them as if they were.
It is also important, as Kant observed, that discoveries in mathematics are
characterised by being about necessity and impossibility
(two sides of the same coin since what's impossible is what's necessarily
false). The biological importance of this is that animals that can classify
describable structures and processes and impossible, or as having necessary
consequences, have an enormous biological advantage over those that have to
check everything by collecting masses of statistical evidence and reasoning
probabilistically. For samples of practical uses of such abilities
see
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/changing-affordances.html
Predicting Affordance Changes
and
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/toddler-theorems.html
Toddler Theorems: Case Studies
The kinds of learning, discovery, and practical use of these topological and
geometric facts
are beyond the scope of current (e.g. 2017) AI robot designs and
learning mechanisms, e.g. "deep learning" that depends on probabilistic
reasoning, which can never establish necessity or impossibility.
(This topic is discussed further in
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/ijcai-2017-cog.html)
See also this draft discussion of some of the roles of compositionality in
biological evolution and its products:
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/sloman-compositionality.pdf
(An html version may be added later.)
P-geometry (not yet fully specified) is used to trisect an arbitrary angle.
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/trisect.html
NOTE:
There is a "process" version of the proof of Pythagoras theorem that makes use of a
video. A version implemented in Pop-11 is illustrated in the video in this tutorial:
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/tutorialspythagoras.html
The video attempts to demonstrate the invariance by showing how the shapes and or
sizes of the triangles, squares and rectangles can be changed without changing the
structural relationships.
This was inspired by a demonstration originally provided by Norman Foo, using
different transformations:
http://www.cse.unsw.edu.au/~norman/Pythag.html
One of the striking facts about Pythagoras' theorem is how many different ways it can
be, and has been, proved.
NB: The programs that present such proofs do not themselves understand the proofs. They can be powerful "cognitive prosthetics" for humans learning mathematics, but the programs do not know what they have done, or why they have done it, and do not understand the invariants involved -- e.g. essentially the same proof could have started with a triangle with different angles, or a triangle of a different size.
The proof of the angle sum of a triangle that you attribute to Mary Pardoe was first published by Bernhard Friedrich Thibaut (1775-1832) in the second edition of his Grundriss der reinen Mathematik, published in Goettingen by Vandenhoek und Ruprecht in 1809 (see page 363).It is not valid without assuming an equivalent of the parallel postulate. In Euclidean geometry, the composition of three rotations by (directed) angles adding up to an integer multiple of a full turn is a translation; but this fails to be true without the parallel postulate. Thibaut had put forward the proof as part of an attempted proof of the parallel postulate; his attempted proof is discussed in Roberto Bonola's Non-Euclidean geometry: a critical and historical study of its development (page 63), in William Barrett Frankland's Theories of parallelism: an historical critique (page 37), and in Jean-Claude Pont's L'aventure des paralleles histoire de la geometrie non-Euclidenne: Precurseurs et attardes (pages 240-244).
Thus the proof is only valid for plane geometry where the plane is assumed to have the properties that it does in Euclid's Elements; it does not hold for the hyperbolic plane of Bolyai and Lobachevsky (which satisfies all those properties bar the parallel postulate). (This is likely why the objection about the surface of a sphere was raised to you.)
The objection that the surface of a sphere provides a counterexample is also over a century old, going back to Olaus Henrici's criticism of Thibaut's proof in "The axioms of geometry", published in Nature, Volume 29, 1884, pp.453-454 and 573.
Reply to Tim Penttila:
I am very grateful for this information. A small point of clarification,
regarding this comment:
"It is not valid without assuming an equivalent of the parallel postulate."
That is exactly why some years ago I began, but did not finish, an exploration
of the possibility of revising Euclidean geometry, as mentioned above, by
replacing the parallel postulate with an axiom related to rotating and
translating line segments, which I called (provisionally) "P-geometry" to
reflect the inspiration of Mary Pardoe. My incomplete discussion is here:
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/p-geometry.html
The possibility of alternative axiomatic presentations of Euclidean geometry is
a reflection of the fact that we have some deeper pre-axiomatic understanding of
space, that allows us to discover truths that can be organised in terms of
axioms, proofs and theorems. All presentations of Euclidean geometry explicitly
or implicitly start with some set of axioms/postulates. As in many other fields
of mathematics those axioms are not arbitrarily selected collections of symbols,
but reflect mathematical discoveries that provide important facts from which
other facts can be inferred. However those axioms are not *uniquely* correct
starting points. They are all discoveries based on something deeper that, as far
as I know has never been accurately identified. It must have been a product of
biological evolution. See the Meta-Morphogenesis project for more on this:
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/meta-morphogenesis.html
Her key idea was to use a theorem (which she apparently re-discovered!) about
the sum of external angles of a polygon always being a whole rotation (360
degrees) and combining that with the fact that each of the external
angles has an
internal angle as complement, as explained in more detail below.
Figure Ang4:
It should be obvious from the figure that it presents a proof that the exterior anti-clockwise
angles of a triangle (A+B+C) sum to a circle (360 degrees) as do the exterior clockwise
angles, not shown in the figure.
Added 19 Mar 2013: This was named "The total turtle trip theorem"
by Seymour Papert,
in his Mindstorms: Children, Computers, and Powerful Ideas (1978), though it was well
known long before then. (It can be generalised to smooth simple closed curves. See also
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Total_curvature .)
The exterior anti-clockwise angles are those obtained by extending each side in turn in one direction then rotating the extension to line up with the next side. So, for example, in Figure Ang4, the internal angles are a, b and c; whereas the exterior anti-clockwise angles A, B and C are got by extending the first side to location 1 then rotating the extension through angle A to the next side, then extending that side to location 2 and rotating the extension through angle B to the second side, and so on.
Because results of all those rotations bring the rotated arrows back to the original orientation, indicated at 1 in the figure, and the rotated arrow does not pass through its original direction, the total external anti-clockwise rotation must be a full circle (i.e. 360 degrees). An exercise left to the reader is to show that that's true not only for triangles but for all polygons, and, by symmetry, must also be true for the sum of the clockwise external angles.
Note: There is a related "visual" proof posted here https://twitter.com/thingswork/status/1121857148068065280 (drawn to my attention by Ron Chrisley), based on what happens if a polygon shrinks to a point. This version applies only to polygons and does does not generalise (smoothly) into a proof that a tangent arrow moving around any simple closed curve, back to its starting point must have a resultant rotation of 360 degrees.Returning to Fig. Ang4, above, for the special case of a triangle, Kay Hughes argued as follows
But each of the internal angles is the complement of the adjacent internal angle,
because they sum to a straight line. So we have these three truths:
A + a = 180 therefore a = 180 - ASo, the sum of the internal angles is
B + b = 180 therefore b = 180 - A
C + c = 180 therefore c = 180 - A
Compare this with the video proof for the external angles posted on Twitter mentioned above: https://twitter.com/thingswork/status/1121857148068065280. This does not generalise easily to the corresponding "total turn theorem" concerning an arbitrary closed, non-self-crossing route in a plane.
I tried searching online for a version of Kay's proof of the triangle sum theorem using Fig. Ang4, and did not find a previous occurrence, though many web sites mention both the triangle sum theorem for interior angles and the theorem about exterior angles always summing to 360.
NOTE (Added 25 Apr 2016): Michael Fourman
(https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Michael_Fourman)
informs me that he encountered the external angle proof while at school.
Graham Nerlich, 1991, How Euclidean Geometry Has Misled Metaphysics, The Journal of Philosophy,
88, 4, Apr, 1991 pp. 169--189,
http://www.jstor.org/stable/2026946
It points out that a common philosophical argument, namely that if everything were to gradually double in linear dimensions during a period of time that would be undetectable, and therefore there is no such thing as absolute size, breaks down if space is non-Euclidean.
This has implications for the status of the Pardoe proof, but also the status of
other proofs in Euclidean geometry. I may later add some comments about that
here. See also the discussion of P-geometry:
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/p-geometry.html
See also this discussion of "Toddler Theorems":
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/toddler-theorems.html
(Or http://goo.gl/QgZU1)
These examples of varieties of necessity and impossibility are closely
related:
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/impossible.html
There is a draft, incomplete, discussion of transitions in information-processing in biological evolution, development, learning, etc. here. That document and this one are both parts of the Meta-Morphogenesis project, partly inspired by Turing's 1952 paper on morphogenesis.
This discussion of theorems about processes that alter or preserve areas of triangles is closely related: http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/triangle-theorem.html
These discussions draw attention to common confusions about the nature of embodied cognition in 'enactivist' theories, and illustrate the need to distinguish 'online intelligence' from 'offline intelligence'.
Related Video On Adam Ford's Web Site
At the AGI conference in Oxford, December 2012, Adam Ford interviewed me about this
and related topics. I used the triangle sum theorem as an example in the interview,
available at http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=iuH8dC7Snno
Offers of help in making progress will be accepted gratefully, especially suggestions regarding mechanisms that could enable robots to have an intuitive understanding of space and time that would enable some of them to rediscover Euclidean geometry, including Mary Pardoe's proof.
I believe that could turn out to be a deep vindication of Immanuel Kant's philosophy of mathematics. Some initial thoughts are in my online talks, including
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/talks/#toddler
Why (and how) did biological evolution produce mathematicians?http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/ijcai-2017-cog.html
Video presentation with online notes:
Why can't (current) machines reason like Euclid or even human toddlers?
(And many other intelligent animals)
Prepared for AGA Workshop at IJCAI 2017.Video of presentation at Oxford Mathematical Institute Conference on Models of Consciousness, Sept 2019:
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=0DTYh37U8uE19 Oct 2018: A summary and discussion of Turing's 1938 views on intuition and ingenuity in mathematics:
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/turing-intuition.html (also (pdf).
https://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/evo-devo-figs.html
Link inserted 11 Oct 2022
NOTE: Turing on continuously changing chemical processes
In 1952 Turing published a paper entitled
"The Chemical Basis Of Morphogenesis",
in
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society. London B,
pp. 37--72,
https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.1952.0012
The abstract states: "The purpose of this paper is to discuss a possible
mechanism by which the genes of a zygote may determine the anatomical structure
of the resulting organism". But the paper focuses only on 2D structure/pattern
formation, which is clearly a relatively simple special sub-category of types of
spatial structure formation.
I suspect that at that time he was working on a deeper, broader research project investing roles of chemistry in controlling assembly of 3D structures and also roles for chemistry in brain mechanisms for reasoning that are implemented in chemical mechanisms rather than in trainable neural networks that merely collect statistical evidence and derive probabilities.
The 1952 paper provided only examples from the 2D subset of structures/patterns whose formation could be explained by combinations of reaction and diffusion, but I suspect he was secretly working on a far more ambitious account of 3D structure formation, and perhaps related abilities to reason about more general forms of spatial structure formation.
Clearly, chemistry-based 2D pattern formation could not explain the formation of 3D chemical structures and mechanisms in brains and other parts of animal bodies. A much richer variety of chemical mechanisms is required in order to account for the formation of 3D chemical structures in living organisms.
A 2D structure cannot have a tube going all the way through it. So an organism implemented as a 2D structure cannot have an alimentary canal, that persists during a variety of spatial motions and deformations, whereas a 3D structure can.
This is a serious limitation of Conway's "Game of Life" which many researchers trying to use Conway's model to explain biological phenomena, seem not to have noticed. I suspect Turing must have been aware of the difference, but I have not come across evidence that he was.
Maintained by
Aaron Sloman
School of Computer Science
The University of Birmingham