NOTES FOR TALK
Cogs Seminar Presentation
Sussex University
16th Feb 2021
Chemistry vs neurones -- pre- and post-natal spatial intelligence, in
chickens, foals, and mathematicians!
SPEAKER:
Aaron Sloman
BACKGROUND NOTE:
I am very pleased to have this opportunity to present the latest developments in a
line of research pursued at Sussex University from 1964 to 1991, extending my
thesis work in Oxford, where I switched from mathematics to philosophy, in order
to defend Kant's philosophy of mathematics against commonplace but misguided
criticisms by philosophers. logicians and mathematicians. This talk continues that
theme.
EXTENDED ABSTRACT:
I'll offer a new, biology-based, line of defence for Immanuel Kant's view of
ancient discoveries in geometry, with implications for spatial consciousness in
humans and other animals, including requirements for spatial consciousness in
newly-hatched chicks, and other animals with sophisticated unlearned competences
available soon after birth or hatching, e.g. foals that can walk to suckle, and
can run with the herd to escape a predator soon after birth. Many animals have
spatial competences before they have had time to learn them. I'll suggest that
those competences, including human mathematical competences, are based on brain
assembling chemical mechanisms -- not empirical learning.
In humans and some other intelligent species those brain-assembling mechanisms can
also provide mechanisms able to detect and make use of impossibility or necessity
in spatial structures and processes -- key features of mathematical competences,
which Kant pointed out (in 1781) could not be based on repeated failures or
successes in empirical learning. Statistical/probabilistic reasoning cannot
establish necessity or impossibility. Instead an overview of relevant
possibilities and their structural limits is required.
I'll sketch the outlines of a theory of how, during reproduction, chemical
processes can produce not only physical structures but also spatial reasoning
abilities used by ancient mathematicians. E.g. Pythagoras' theorm was discovered
and proved many times long before Pythagoras was born.
A key feature of the theory is that the chemical mechanisms that assemble many
kinds of body parts also provide abilities to detect spatial necessity and
impossibility. The need for that arises during genetically driven assembly of
increasingly complex and varied structures.
The earliest assembly processes are constrained/supported by the double helix
structure of DNA, but as components become more complex so must the assembly
mechanisms become more sophisticated, e.g. controlling construction and assembly
of increasingly complex and varied physiological components of the new organism.
In the early stages the items assembled within a cell are tiny molecular
structures, with few components, but at later stages far larger, more complex and
more varied multi-cellular structures are constructed and assembled in required
spatial configurations. The chemical control mechanisms doing the assembly need to
become increasingly sophisticated at later stages, e.g. using new kinds of
information about spatial structures and relationships between parts that have
already been assembled.
Many scientists and AI engineers (e.g. the designers of Deep Mind) now believe
that such intelligence has to be implemented in trainable neural nets, but that
cannot apply to mechanisms building the neural nets before a functional brain has
been constructed.
Key idea:
If the later, more complex, assembly processes require abilities to detect
possibilities and constraints (impossibilities) in choosing what to do next
by reasoning rather than trial and error (which would explode the time required
for assembly, and possibly lead to too many fatal mistakes), then not only the
components of the new organism, but also the components of the construction
mechanisms building the organism, must be developed chemically, including their
information-processing abilities required for controlling increasingly complex
construction processes.
In a subset of organisms, evolution seems to have found ways of making those
spatial reasoning competences available also to the completed organism, as shown
by spatial intelligence in squirrels, nest-building birds, foals that can run with
the herd within hours of birth, and others. In a small subset of those species,
most obviously humans, the processes of learning to detect and use spatial
impossiblity and necessity continue after birth, presumably still somehow using
sub-celluar chemical control mechanisms for spatial reasoning that were previously
used to control assembly of the organism.
In humans, additional reflective mechanisms continue to be built after birth, so
that (as Piaget discovered) they can make proto-mathematical discoveries, such as
the necessary transitivity of one-to-one correspondence in the fifth or sixth
year. This is a pre-requisite for a full understanding of numbers and their uses
in counting sets.
There are many gaps still to be filled in this theory, including explaining in
detail how the chemical bootstrapping mechanisms originally provided by DNA extend
themselves at later stages in a developing organism so as to include useful
abilities to detect impossibility and necessity, required for effective control of
assembly of more complex physiological structures and mechanisms -- a process
children playing with construction kits such as Meccano, Lego, Tinker-toys,
Fischer-technic, etc. develop spontaneously and unwittingly and use in controlling
more complex assembly processes. Other intelligent species seem to have similar
abilities, though only humans seem to be able to go on to reflect on, discuss, and
explicitly teach such competences. But the core mechanisms are needed in the
initial assembly of all organisms that grow themselves starting from fertilised
egg-cells.
The requirements are different in organisms like trees that do not move about as a
whole, though their life cycles involve many motions of parts.
The genetically based mechanisms that develop spatial reasoning competences during
reproduction are important because understanding of (e.g. spatial) impossibility
(and necessity) cannot be learnt empirically, e.g. because no amount of failure
proves impossibility. This also points to serious limitations of artificial neural
nets whose learning is based entirely on collection of statistics and derivation
of probabilities.
More than mere failure, or success, is required to explain reasons for failure or
success. It also requires insight into the structures of problems: the type of
insight without which the development of many types and branches of mathematics,
and their application in practical activities, e.g. making clothes, building
shelters, building machines to help with construction processes, would have been
impossible. The recently fashionable theory that mathematical competences depend
on uses of symbolic, logic-based, reasoning cannot account for the much older
forms of mathematical discovery based on spatial reasoning abilities, some of
which seem to be partially shared with other intelligent species.
So we need alternatives to both logic-based symbolic reasoning mechanisms and
statistics-based probabilistic reasoning to explain spatial mathematical
intelligence, or to replicate it in future machines.
A related line of thought may have motivated Alan Turing's very surprising
investigations of chemical morphogenesis, reported in his 1952 paper, but
without any mention of this motive. However, there is a sentence about the
importance of chemistry in brains in his Mind 1950 paper that seems to be
relevant. Also relevant is the distinction he made in his thesis between
mathematical ingenuity and mathematical intuition, claiming that unlike
human mathematicians (Turing-equivalent) computers are capable of mathematical
ingenuity but not mathematical intuition. He did not explain why not.
These ideas are related to, but different from, claims made and developed by
Roger Penrose since 1989 (in The Emperor's New Mind) and in subsequent work partly
in collaboration with Stuart Hameroff, illustrated in a recent joint presentation
online here:
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=xGbgDf4HCHU
Consciousness and the physics of the brain
May 12, 2020
They don't seem to have noticed the role of multi-stage chemistry-based
intelligence required during construction of a new complex organism (including
construction of brains) starting from a fertilised egg-cell, Perhaps the
microtubules occurring during development of a foetus are relevant long before the
microtubules in brains, emphasised by Hameroff.
(See https://science.sciencemag.org/content/357/6354/882.1)
There is still a vast amount of work to be done, combining and extending what has
been learnt so far about biochemical mechanisms and processes. Perhaps, as Penrose
suggests, current physical theory will need a major extension. Or perhaps
implications of what is already known about quantum chemistry will suffice. There
may already be important relevant insights in Schrodinger's later writings that I
have not yet taken in.
Further notes
There is fragmentary evidence that Alan Turing was thinking about a project of
this sort when he wrote his 1952 paper on chemistry-based morphogenesis,
explaining formation of surface patterns on organisms, while his unstated
long-term intention was much deeper and more important than explaining how
visible patterns form. The label "Meta-Morphogenesis" was introduced to refer
to that more ambitious project in Sloman(2013).
\cite{Sloman-Turing--4}.
Continued development of
the project since then is reported in a growing collection of online documents referenced in
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/meta-morphogenesis.html
,
which include a theory of evolved construction-kits, including construction-kits
created during processes of development of individual organisms in fertilized
eggs, or seeds.
There seems to be little or no recognition of these processes and their
implications in current philosophy of mind, psychology, neuroscience and AI. So
theories developed in those fields are incapable of producing adequate
explanations of a variety of phenomena, including spatial learning and reasoning
in many species, ancient processes of mathematical discovery in geometry and
topology, long before Euclid, and important aspects of human consciousness,
including forms of proto-consciousness involved in multiple layers of
increasingly complex information-based control mechanisms during development
from fertilised eggs. Insofar as the key processes crucially involve both
discrete and continuous change they cannot be fully replicated on digital
computers, though they can be implemented in chemical processes for reasons
pointed out in Schrödinger's 1944 Book, though he
apparently did not notice their importance beyond explaining the possibility of
reliable biological reproduction.
Background
Development of this "tangled network" of ideas began in 1958/9 when I switched
from mathematics to philosophical research on the nature of mathematical
discovery, defending Kant's view of mathematical
knowledge as non-empirical, synthetic (not derived from definitions using
logic), and concerned with necessary truths and necessary falsehoods
(impossibilities). This led to a DPhil thesis (Oxford) in 1962. I later felt the
claims and arguments could be improved, after encountering Artificial
Intelligence, and learning to program, starting around 1970. A book,
The Computer Revolution in Philosophy, resulted in 1978. It was later
digitised and placed online at
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/crp/
then repeatedly updated/extended with references to related AI topics and
projects.
A full account of what minds and brains can do would have to explain how ancient
mathematical brains made discoveries in geometry
and topology centuries before Euclid, using forms of spatial reasoning processes
that make it possible to detect examples of impossibility
and necessity. I don't think anyone currently understands how brains
represent and detect, spatial/geometric
impossibility and necessity.
This is not a general requirement for models of mind, e.g. models of affective
states and processes, e.g. desires, emotions, attitudes, etc. using
information-processing architectures containing multiple interacting
sub-systems, discussed in
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/vm-functionalism.html
In contrast, pre-verbal human toddlers, illustrated in
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/toddler-theorems.html
nest-building in weaver-birds and crows, and spatial intelligence in squirrels,
elephants, orangutans, dolphins, octopuses and many other species, require
abilities to represent and reason about necessity
and impossibility,
closely related to ancient mathematical abilities. Probabilistic neural nets
cannot represent or reason about these modalities.
There is still a great deal to explain about varieties
of spatial monitoring and control not only in whole organisms but also in
enormously complex and little understood chemical control and assembly processes
in eggs that produce chickens, alligators and other animals, and in related
construction processes and mechanisms in mammalian reproduction.
I am sure that if Alan Turing had not died in 1954 he would by now have taken
these ideas much further than I have -- and in the process explaining his
obscure distinction between mathematical intuition and mathematical ingenuity.
https://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/turing-intuition.html
I suspect Turing would have agreed that Mary Pardoe's (re-) discovery of the
non-standard proof of the triangle sum theorem, presented above, was an example
of use of mathematical intuition. She found that her students understood and
remembered it more easily than the standard Euclidean proof that depends on
properties of parallel lines.
Note for philosophy teachers
I suggest that, in view of what we now know about life, and the rate at which
such knowledge is being extended, teaching philosophy of mind and philosophy of
mathematics without teaching any evolutionary and developmental biology is
educationally misguided.
References
Chicken embryo development
http://www.poultryhub.org/physiology/body-systems/embryology-of-the-chicken/
Photographs of chick embryo stages (PDF):
http://www.poultryhub.org/wp-content/uploads/2012/05/Poster_Chick_Embryo_Dev_English.pdf
LOCAL COPY FOR LECTURE
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/~axs/fig/chicken-egg-devel.jpg
apa-stuff.d/Poster_Chick_Embryo_Dev_English.pdf
DAY 1: Appearance of embryonic tissue.
DAY 2: Tissue development very visible. Appearance of blood vessels.
DAY 3: Heart beats. Blood vessels very visible.
DAY 4: Eye pigmented.
DAY 5: Appearance of elbows and knees.
DAY 6: Appearance of beak. Voluntary movements begin.
DAY 7: Comb growth begins. Egg tooth begins to appear.
DAY 8: Feather tracts seen. Upper and lower beak equal in length.
DAY 9: Embryo starts to look bird-like. Mouth opening occurs.
DAY 10: Egg tooth prominent. Toe nails visible.
DAY 11: Cob serrated. Tail feathers apparent.
DAY 12: Toes fully formed. First few visible feathers.
DAY 13: Appearance of scales. Body covered lightly with feathers.
DAY 14: Embryo turns head towards large end of egg.
DAY 15: Gut is drawn into abdominal cavity.
DAY 16: Feathers cover complete body. Albumen nearly gone.
DAY 17: Amniotic fluid decreases. Head is between legs.
DAY 18: Growth of embryo nearly complete. Yolk sac remains outside of embryo. Head is under right wing.
DAY 19: Yolk sac draws into body cavity. Amniotic fluid gone. Embryo occupies most of space within egg (not in the air cell).
DAY 20: Yolk sac drawn completely into body. Embryo becomes a chick (breathing air with its lungs). Internal and external pipping occurs.
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=PhOqP_GasVs
Baby Crocs Hone Hunting Skills -- National Geographic
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=nOkq69T6j7E
Ducklings first feed after hatching. First Swimming baby ducks.
Hatched without mother. (Incubated??)
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=9jRSgZVhWvw
Baby chicks with hen.
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=OsoNKlyFtpI
Chimpanzees React to Their Reflections in a Mirror
CenterForGreatApes
https://video.nationalgeographic.com/video/00000144-0a34-d3cb-a96c-7b3dd2970000
Mother crocodile takes babies swimming, to hunt for food.
William Bechtel, Adele Abrahamsen and Benjamin Sheredos,
(2018),
Using diagrams to reason about biological mechanisms, in
Diagrammatic representation and inference,
Eds. P. Chapman, G. Stapleton, A. Moktefi, S. Perez-Kriz and F. Bellucci,
Springer,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-91376-6_26
Godfrey-Smith, P. (2007). Innateness and Genetic Information. In P. Carruthers,
S. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.),
The Innate Mind Volume 3: Foundations and the Future
(pp. 55-105). OUP.
https://petergodfreysmith.com/PGS-InfoAndInnate.pdf
Godfrey-Smith, P. (2017).
Other Minds: The Octopus and the Evolution of Intelligent Life,
William Collins.
Carl G. Hempel (1945),
Geometry and Empirical Science, in
American Mathematical Monthly, 52, 1945,
also in Readings in Philosophical Analysis
eds. H. Feigl and W. Sellars,
New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1949,
http://www.ditext.com/hempel/geo.html
Kant, Immanuel (1781).
Critique of pure reason,
(Translated (1929) by Norman Kemp Smith),
London: Macmillan. Retrieved from
https://archive.org/details/immanuelkantscri032379mbp/page/n10/mode/2up
Piaget, J. (1952). The Child's Conception of Number. London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul.
Schrödinger, E. (1944). What is life? Cambridge: CUP.
A. Sloman, (1965) `Necessary', `A Priori' and `Analytic', in
Analysis 26, pp. 12--16,
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/62-80.html#1965-02
Sloman, A. (2013). Virtual machinery and evolution of mind (part 3)
Meta-morphogenesis: Evolution of information-processing machinery.
In S. B. Cooper & J. van Leeuwen (Eds.),
Alan Turing - His Work and Impact (p. 849-856),
Amsterdam: Elsevier.
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/11.html#1106d
Aaron Sloman, 2013,
Virtual Machinery and Evolution of Mind (Part 3)
Meta-Morphogenesis: Evolution of Information-Processing Machinery,
in
Alan Turing - His Work and Impact,
Ed. S. B. Cooper and J. van Leeuwen,
pp. 849-856,
Elsevier,
Amsterdam,
9780123869807,
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/11.html#1106d
A. M. Turing, 1952, The Chemical Basis Of Morphogenesis,
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. London B 237, 237, pp. 37--72,
MORE REFS
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=hFZFjoX2cGg
Building the Perfect Squirrel Proof Bird Feeder (Failed?)
Also some other animals.
https://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/movies/apa/videos.txt
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=9jRSgZVhWvw
Hens and chicks
MURGI Hen Harvesting Eggs to Chicks new "BORN" Roosters and Hens Small Birds
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=QPqcSKhtxKk
Ducklings around the lake. (4.24 starting to paddle)
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=KBm698UoROs
Newly Hatched Ducklings [2008] --
All waiting for last eggs to hatch.
'Peak hype': why the driverless car revolution has stalled
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=QPqcSKhtxKk
PYTHAGORAS wikipedia
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Pythagorean_theorem
The above is a small sample of references relevant to this talk.
More will be added later.
Maintained by
Aaron Sloman
School of Computer Science
The University of Birmingham
-----