First characterise the gulf accurately!
Aaron Sloman
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/~axs
University of Birmingham, UK
Yet there remain huge chasms between artificial systems and forms of natural
intelligence in humans and other animals -- including weaver-birds, elephants,
squirrels, dolphins, orangutans, carnivorous mammals, and their prey.
(Sample weaver bird cognition here:
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=6svAIgEnFvw.)
Fashionable "paradigms" offering definitive answers come and go (sometimes reappearing with new labels). Yet no AI or robotic systems come close to modelling or replicating the development from helpless infant over a decade or two to plumber, cook, trapeze artist, bricklayer, seamstress, dairy farmer, shop-keeper, child-minder, professor of philosophy, concert pianist, mathematics teacher, quantum physicist, waiter in a busy restaurant, etc. Human and animal developmental trajectories vastly outstrip, in depth and breadth of achievement, the products of artificial learning systems, although AI systems sometimes produce super-human competences in restricted domains, such as proving logical theorems, winning at chess or Jeopardy, and perhaps playing table tennis at championship level one day in the distant future? (http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=tIIJME8-au8).
I'll outline a very long-term multi-disciplinary research programme addressing these and other inadequacies in current AI, robotics, psychology, neuroscience and philosophy of mathematics and mind, in part by building on past work, and in part by looking for very different clues and challenges: the Meta-Morphogenesis project, partly inspired by Turing's work on morphogenesis. http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/meta-morphogenesis.html
Note:
Ths project is unfunded and I have no plans to apply for funding, though
others may do so if they wish.
There are many ways in which current robots and AI systems fall short of the intelligence of humans and other animals, including their ability to reason about topology and continuous deformation (for examples see Sauvy and Sauvy 1974 and this document). Don't expect any robot (even with soft hands and compliant joints) to be able to dress a two year old child (safely) in the near future, a task that requires understanding of both topology and deformable materials, among other things. (As illustrated in this video.) Understanding why things work and don't work lags even further behind abilities to perform tasks, often achieved by programming or training. For example, understanding why it's not a good idea to start putting on a shirt by inserting a hand into a cuff and pulling the sleeve up over the arm requires a combination of topological and metrical reasoning: -- a type of mathematical child-minding theorem, not taught in schools but understood by most child-minders, even if they have never articulated the theorem and cannot articulate the reasons why it is true. Can you? Merely pointing at past evidence showing that attempts to dress a child that way always fails does not explain why it is impossible.
What sequence of movements could get the shirt onto the child if the shirt is made of material that is flexible but does not stretch much? Why would it be a mistake to start by pulling the cuff over the hand, or pushing the head through the neck-hole? What difference would it make if the material could be stretched arbitrarily without being permanently changed?
In more obviously mathematical domains, where computers are commonly assumed to excel, the achievements are narrowly focused on branches of mathematics using inference methods based on arithmetic, algebra, logic, probability and statistical theory.
However, mathematics is much broader than that, and we lack models of the reasoning (for instance geometrical and topological reasoning) that enabled humans to come up with the profoundly important and influential mathematical discoveries reported in Euclid's Elements 2.5 millennia ago -- arguably the single most important book ever written on this planet. The early pioneers could not have learnt from mathematics teachers. How did they teach themselves, and each other?
Those mathematical capabilities seem to have deep, but mostly unnoticed, connections with animal abilities to perceive practically important types of affordance, including use of mechanisms that are concerned not only with the perceiver's possibilities for immediate action but more generally with what is and is not possible in a perceived situation and how those possibilities and impossibilities can change, for example if something is moved.
Many animals, including pre-verbal humans, need to be able to perceive and think about such things, though in most cases without having the ability to reflect on their thinking or to communicate the thoughts to someone else. The latter meta-cognitive abilities evolve later in the history of a species and develop later in individuals.
Thinking about what would be possible in various possible states of affairs is totally different from abilities to make predictions about what will happen, or to reason probabilistically. It's one thing to try repeatedly to push a shirt on a child by pushing its hand and arm in through the end of a sleeve and conclude from repeated failures that success is improbable. It's quite another thing to understand that if the shirt material cannot be stretched, then success is impossible (for a normally shaped child and a well fitting shirt) though if the material could be stretched as much as needed then it could be done. Additional reasoning powers might enable the machine to work out that starting by pushing the head in through the largest opening could require least stretching, and to work this out without having to collect statistics from repeated attempts.
It is possible to have a shallow (statistical) predictive capability based on observed regularities while lacking deeper knowledge about the set of possibilities sampled in those observations. A more complex example is the difference between (a) having heard and remembered a set of sentences and noticed some regular associations between pairs of words in those sentences and (b) being aware of the generative grammar used by the speakers, or having acquired such a grammar unconsciously. The grasp of the grammar, using recursive modes of composition, permits a much richer and more varied collection of utterances to be produced or understood. Something similar is required for visual perception of spatial configurations and spatial processes that are even richer and more varied than sentences can be. Yet we share that more powerful competence with more species.
Conceivably a robot could be programmed to explore making various movements combining a shirt and a flexible, child-shaped doll. It might discover one or more sequences of moves that successfully get the shirt on, provided that the shirt and doll are initially in one of the robot's previously encountered starting states. This could be done by exploring the space of sequences of possible moves, whose size would depend on the degree of precision of its motion and control parameters. For example, if from every position of the hands there are 50 possible 3-D directions of movement and the robot tries 20 steps after each starting direction, then the number of physical trajectories from the initial state to be explored is
and if it tries a million new moves every second, then it could explore that space in about 302408000000000000 millennia. Clearly animals do something different when they learn to do things, but exactly how they chose things to try at each moment is not known.
The "generative grammar" of spatial structures and processes is rich and deep, and is not concerned only with linear sequences discrete sequences. In fact there are multiple overlapping space-time grammars, involving different collections of objects assembled, disassembled, moved, repaired, etc. and used, often for many purposes and in many ways.
There are different overlapping subsets of spatio-temporal possibilities, with different mathematical structures, including Euclidean and non-Euclidean geometries (e.g. the geometry of the surface of a hand, or face is non-euclidean) and various subsets of topology. Mechanisms for for acquiring and using these "possibility subsets", i.e. possible action sequences and trajectories seem to be used by pre-verbal children and other animals. That suggests that those abilities, must have evolved before linguistic capabilities. They seem to be at work in young children playing with toys before they can understand or speak a human language. The starting capabilities extended through much spatial exploration, seem to provide much of the subject matter (semantic content) for many linguistic communications.
The early forms of reasoning and learning in young humans, and corresponding subsets in other animals, are beyond the scope of current AI theorem provers, planners, reasoners, or learning systems that I know of. Those forms seem to be used by non-human intelligent animals that are able to perceive both possibilities and constraints on possibilities in spatial configurations. Betty, a New Caledonian crow, made headline news in 2002 when she surprised Oxford researchers by making a hook from a straight piece of wire, in order to lift a bucket of food out of a vertical glass tube. Moreover, in a series of repeated challenges she made multiple hooks, using at least four very different strategies, taking advantage of different parts of the environment, all apparently in full knowledge of what she was doing and why -- as there was no evidence of random trial and error behaviour. Why did she not go on using the earlier methods, which all worked? Several of the videos showing the diversity of techniques are still available here: http://users.ox.ac.uk/~kgroup/tools/movies.shtml
It is very unlikely that you have previously encountered and solved the problem posed below the following image, yet many people very quickly think of a solution.
Suppose you wanted to use one hand to lift the mug to a nearby
table without any part of your skin coming into contact with
the mug, and without moving the book on which the mug is resting,
what could you do, using only one hand?
Another set of example action strategies is provided by the following two images.
Consider one or more sequences of actions that would enable
you to change the physical configuration depicted on the left
into the configuration depicted on the right -- not
necessarily in exactly the same locations as the objects
depicted. Then do the same for the actions required to
transform the right configuration to the left one.
When you think about such things even with fairly detailed constraints on the possible motions, you will not be thinking about either the nervous signals sent to the muscles involved, nor the patterns of retinal stimulation that will be provided -- and in fact the same actions can produce different retinal processes depending on the precise position of the head, and the direction of gaze of the eyes, and whether and how the fixation changes during the process. Probably the fixation requirements will be more constrained for a novice at this task than for an expert, but either way humans, and I suspect other animals, do not need to reason about such details if they use an ontology of 3-D structures and processes rather than an ontology of sensory and motor brain signals. Contrast this with the sorts of assumptions discussed in Clark (2013) , and many others who attempt to build theories of cognition on the basis of sensory-motor control loops.
This ability to think about sequences of possible alterations in a physical configuration without actually doing anything, and without having full metrical information, inspired much early work in AI, including the sorts of symbolic planning used by Shakey the Stanford robot and Freddy the Edinburgh robot, though at the time the technology available (including available computer power) was grossly inadequate for the task, including ruling out visual servo control of actions.
The capabilities and information-processing requirements supporting them that I have been discussing are ignored by researchers who claim that intelligent robots require only the right physical mode of interaction with the environment, not central reasoning capabilities. Some have supported this claim by referring to or demonstrating "passive walkers" http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=N64KOQkbyiI. Try putting a brick in front of a passive walker. I'll refrain from naming and embarrassing authors who, for a while, enthusiastically used such toys as pointers to a "New artificial intelligence", using labels such as "embodied", "enactivist", "behaviour based", and "situated", to characterise their new acclaimed paradigm -- not realising that those approaches are at least as selective as the older reasoning based approaches that they criticised. (Some of that history was presented in Boden (2006).
The requirements for perception and action mechanisms differ according to which "central" layers the organism has. For instance, for an organism able to use deliberative capabilities to think of evaluate and select multi-step plans, where most of the actions will occur in situations that do not exist yet, it is not enough to identify objects and their relationships (pencil, mug, handle of mug, book, window-frame, etc.) in a current visual percept. It is also necessary to be able to "think ahead" about possible actions at a suitable level of abstraction, derived from what is perceived.
This ability to reason about possible actions at a level of generality that
abstracts from metrical details seems to be closely related to the abilities of
ancient Greeks to make mathematical discoveries about possible configurations of
lines and circles and the consequences of changing those configurations, without
being tied to particular lengths, angles, curvatures, etc., in Euclidean
geometry or topology. As far as I know, no current robot can do this, and
neuroscientists don't know how brains do it. Some examples of mathematical
reasoning that could be related to reasoning about practical tasks and which are
currently beyond what AI reasoners can do, are presented here:
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/torus.html
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/triangle-sum.html
In 1971 I presented a paper at an AI conference (IJCAI) arguing that the focus solely on logic-based reasoning could hold up progress in AI, because it ignored forms of spatial reasoning that had proved powerful in mathematics and practical problem solving. I did not realise then how difficult it would be to explain exactly what the alternatives were and how they worked -- despite many conferences and journal papers on diagrammatic reasoning since then. There have also been several changes of fashion promoted by various AI researchers (or their critics) including use of neural nets, constraint nets, evolutionary algorithms, dynamical systems, behaviour-based systems, embodied cognition, situated cognition, enactive cognition, autopoesis, morphological computation, statistical learning, bayesian nets, and probably others that I have not encountered, often accompanied by hand-waving and hyperbole without much science. In parallel with this there has been continued research advancing older paradigms for symbolic and logic based, theorem proving, planning, and grammar based language processing. Several of the debates are analysed in Boden(2006).[REF]
There are many other inadequacies in current AI, including, for example the lack of an agreed framework for relating information-processing architectures to requirements in engineering contexts or to explanatory models in scientific contexts (e.g. attempts to model emotions, or learning capabilities, in humans or other animals. I also think we are using a seriously restricted set of forms of representation (means of encoding information) partly because of the educational backgrounds of researchers (as a result of which many of them assume that spatial structures must be represented using mechanisms based on Cartesian coordinates) and partly because of a failure to analyse in sufficient detail the problems overcome by many animals in their natural environments.
Standard research techniques are not applicable to the study of such capabilities in young children and other animals because there is so much individual variation, but the widespread availability of cheap video cameras has led to a large and growing collection of freely available examples.
However, researchers have to learn what to look for. For example, online intelligence requires highly trained precisely controlled responses matched to fine details of the physical environment, e.g. catching a ball, playing table tennis, picking up a box and putting it on another. In contrast offline intelligence involves understanding not just existing spatial configurations but also the possibilities for change and constraints on change, and for some tasks the ability to find sequences of possible changes to achieve a goal, where some of the possibilities are not specified in metrical detail because they do not yet exist. This requires the ability to construct relatively abstract forms of representation of perceived or remembered situations to allow plans to be constructed with missing details that can be acquired later during execution. You can think about making a train trip to another town without having information about where you will stand when purchasing your ticket or which coach you will board when the train arrives. You can think about how to rotate a chair to get it through a doorway without needing information about the precise 3-D coordinates of parts of the chair or knowing exactly where you will grasp it, or how much force you will need to apply at various stages of the move.
There is no reason to believe that humans and other animals have to use probability distributions over possible precise metrical values. Even thinking about such precise values probabilistically is highly unintelligent when reasoning about topological relationships or partial orderings (nearer, thinner, a bigger angle, etc.) is all that's needed, as I have tried to illustrate here: http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/changing-affordances.html Unfortunately, the mathematically sophisticated, but nevertheless unintelligent, modes of thinking are used in many robots, after much statistical learning (to acquire probability distributions) and complex probabilistic reasoning, that is potentially explosive. That is in part a consequence of the unjustified assumption that all spatial properties and relations have to be expressed in Cartesian coordinate systems. Human mathematicians did not know about them when they proved their first theorems about Euclidean geometry.
NOTE to be updated:
It is clear that the earliest spatial cognition could not have used full
euclidean geometry, including its uniform metric. I suspect that the metrical
version of geometry was a result of a collection of transitions adding richer
and richer non-metrical relationships, including networks of partial orderings
of size, distance, angle, speed, curvature, etc. Later indefinitely extendable
partial metrics were added: distance between X and Y is at least three times the
distance between P and Q and at most five times that distance. Such procedures
could allow previously used standards to sub-divided with arbitrarily increasing
precision. At first this must have been applied only to special cases, then
later somehow (using what cognitive mechanisms) extrapolated indefinitely,
implicitly using a Kantian form of potential infinity (long before Kant
realised the need for this). Filling in the details of such a story, and
relating it to varieties of cognition not only in the ancestors of humans but
also many other existing species will be a long term multi-disciplinary
collaborative task, with deep implications for neuroscience, robotics,
psychology, philosophy of mathematics and philosophy of mind. (Among others.)
Moreover, human toddlers appear to be capable of making proto-mathematical discoveries ("toddler theorems") even if they are unaware of what they have done. But the process starts in infancy, e.g. when I saw a 11 month old infant discover, apparently with great delight, that she could hold a ball between her upturned foot and the palm of her hand. (Picture to be added.)
Animal abilities to perceive and use complex novel affordances appear to be closely related. Not only computational models, but also current psychology and neuroscience, don't seem to come close -- especially if we consider not only simple numerical mathematics, on which many psychological studies of mathematics seem to focus, but also topological and geometrical reasoning, and the essentially mathematical ability to discover a generative grammar closely related to the verbal patterns a child has experienced in her locality, where the grammar is very different from those discovered by children exposed to thousands of other languages.
There seem to be key features of some of those developmental trajectories that could provide clues, including some noticed by Piaget and his former colleague, Annette Karmiloff-Smith. (EXPAND)
Partly inspired by one of Alan Turing's last papers (The Chemical Basis of Morphogenesis) (1952), I'll outline a very long term collaborative project for building up an agreed collection of explanatory tasks, and present some ideas about what has been missed in most proposed explanatory theories. Perhaps researchers who disagree, often fruitlessly, about what the answers are can collaborate fruitfully on finding out what the questions are, sine what needs to be explained is far from obvious. The Meta-Morphogenesis project is concerned with trying to understand what varieties of information processing biological evolution has achieved, not only in humans but across the spectrum of life. Many of the achievements are far from obvious.
A
more detailed, but still evolving,
introduction to the project can be found here:
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/meta-morphogenesis.html
____________________________________________________________________________
REFERENCES
(To be extended.)
Maintained by
Aaron Sloman
School of Computer Science
The University of Birmingham