(DRAFT: Liable to change)
A new, shorter, document with overlapping contents is
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/kant-hume-mathematics.html
This is a companion-piece to a discussion of Turing's notion of mathematical
intuition:
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/turing-intuition.html
(also
pdf)
I am grateful to Timothy Chow (http://timothychow.net/) for probing questions and criticisms of an early draft of that paper that made me appreciate the need for a separate outline of Kant's philosophy of mathematics, at least as I interpret it in the context of asking whether Turing had reached fundamentally similar conclusions about the nature of mathematical discovery in his distinction between mathematical intuition and mathematical ingenuity, discussed in the above paper -- also work in progress.
I wrote a thesis (never published, but now freely available online) defending Kant's philosophy of mathematics a long time ago Sloman(1962), but I am not a Kant scholar. For views of established Kant Scholars, see, for example, Posy(Ed, 1992). What's most important for my purposes is not whether the claims made here about spatial mathematical knowledge were previously made by Kant, but whether they are true. I claim they are both true and at least inspired by Kant's insights: i.e. this is an updated version of Kant's philosophy of mathematics, inspired by Kant(1781)!
Some philosophical background is still available only in the above thesis. But
there are many more examples and discussions on this website, some indicated
below, especially the "impossible" web page, discussing abilities to detect,
reason about, and (in some cases) make use of mathematical impossibilities or
necessities:
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/impossible.html
(also
PDF)
A partial index of discussion notes in this directory is in
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/AREADME.html
Roughly, the philosophers I met seemed to accept something like the claim I later discovered David Hume had made, namely that there are only two kinds of knowledge ("Hume's fork"):
(i) relations between ideas, such as explicit definitions and propositions that are derivable from definitions using pure logic (e.g. "All bachelor uncles are unmarried"), and knowledge obtained by "abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number",and
(ii) knowledge obtained by "experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence", including knowledge derived from sensory experience, e.g. using observation and measurement, as in the empirical sciences, or knowledge gained by introspection.
Hume's advice regarding any other claim to knowledge or truth was: "Commit it then to the flames: for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion". I think theology was his main target, along with related metaphysical theories produced by philosophers. But I am not a Hume scholar, and I mention him merely as a backdrop to Kant's claim, originally made in reaction to Hume, that there are not two major categories of knowledge with content, but three, as explained below. (In this discussion I'll ignore interesting sub-divisions within the three categories.)
The Humean philosophers I encountered in Oxford acknowledged that -- unlike discoveries in physics, chemistry, astronomy, biology, history, or snooping on your neighbours -- mathematical discoveries were not empirical, so they concluded that all mathematical knowledge was in Hume's first category, i.e. matters of definition and logic ("relations between ideas").
When I encountered such Humean claims about mathematics, they did not match my own experience of studying mathematics and making mathematical discoveries (as all good mathematics students do, even if their discoveries are re-discoveries). For example, while studying Euclidean geometry at school my classmates and I were often given tasks like "Find a construction that will produce a configuration ..." or "Find a proof that ...". In many cases, success involved using a physical or imagined diagram and performing (physical or imagined) operations on it. Some examples are included below.
Such mathematical discovery processes are very different from performing logical deductions from definitions and axioms.
Moreover, whereas experimenting with diagrams can provide empirical information, e.g. how long it takes to produce the diagram and whether the diagram is similar to some other diagram, in the case of mathematical reasoning with diagrams something deeper happens: we can discover necessary truths and impossibilities that are not mere logical consequences of definitions or hypothetical axioms. They are spatial consequences of other spatial relationships. Like logical consequences of logical relationships these spatial consequences are necessary consequences: counter-examples are impossible.
My own experience of making such discoveries as a mathematics student confirmed what I later discovered was Kant's claim that besides the analytic truths there are additional necessary truths that are synthetic, and which can also be discovered to be true by non-empirical means -- using powers of human brains that are not yet understood, over two centuries later! I'll give several examples below.
The main point of this document is that some of the kinds of mathematical discovery identified by Kant, are not yet replicated on computers, and are not explained by known brain mechanisms, in particular mechanisms based on discovering statistical correlations, and reasoning about probabilities. The well known and highly influential discoveries of ancient mathematicians were concerned with necessity and impossibility, not high or low probabilities.
Mathematical and causal cognition
In many cases the mathematical discoveries are directly related to causation:
e.g. if you change the size of one angle of a triangle, e.g. by moving one of
the ends of the opposite side then that necessarily causes the shape and area of
the triangle to change. Adding exactly one ball to a box containing six balls,
without removing any causes the box to contain seven balls. For more on this
connection, including biological examples, see Chappell & Sloman (2007b).
(a) it is necessarily true that two straight lines cannot bound a finite region of a plane surface, and
(b) it is necessarily true that a set A of objects in one to one correspondence with a set of five objects and a set B of objects in one to one correspondence with a set of three objects, where sets A and B contain no common object, will together form a set in one to one correspondence with every set of eight objects. In other words it is necessarily the case that 5+3=8.
Originally such discoveries were made using cognitive resources that are different from abilities to use modern symbolic logic to derive consequences from definitions, or from arbitrarily chosen axioms used to define a domain of entities.
However, Euclid's axioms were not arbitrary postulates, and (by definition of "axiom") were not derived from other axioms by logical reasoning: they were all ancient mathematical discoveries. Other sets of axioms discovered more recently, e.g. Tarski's axioms, have been shown to suffice to generate all, or important subsets of, Euclidean geometry. But their consequences do not include some of the interesting extensions to Euclidean geometry, e.g. Origami geometry (for more on Origami see Geretschlager(1995) and Wikipedia(2018), and the neusis construction described below.
What if it is not a straight line but a curved line in a plane (flat) surface?
If a line is a closed curve, so that it has no ends, like a circle or ellipse, is there a point that divides it into two equal parts? The answer is: No.
Why? Because if P is a point on a closed curve L, such as a circle, or ellipse, or banana shaped curve, the portions of the line on each side of P are connected via a route that does not pass through P, so P does not divide the line into two parts. So it cannot divide the line into two equal parts.
Is it always possible to use two points to divide a closed curve into two equal parts?
Can a planar triangle have one side whose length is greater than the combined lengths of the other two sides, and if not why not?
If S is a sphere resting on a planar horizontal surface H, much larger than the surface of S, and P is a point on the sphere other than the point of contact with H and there are no nearby objects impeding the motion of the sphere, is it possible to roll S smoothly, without any slipping, along H until P is in contact with H? If so, how many different rolling trajectories can achieve this?
The examples in the last few paragraphs will be trivial for experienced mathematicians, but should allow non-mathematicians to have the personal experience of making a mathematical discovery, before thinking about whether, and how their discovery process could be replicated on a computer. Additional examples are below, and online at Sloman(2015-18).
An experienced mathematician can (sometimes) produce a set of axioms expressed in a logical formalism with some symbols referring to geometric entities, properties and relationships, and then derive theorems from the axioms using logic, as the great mathematician David Hilbert did when he "axiomatized" Euclidean geometry Hilbert(1899). But many lesser humans can make discoveries as the ancient mathematicians did, by thinking about spatial structures and transformations of spatial structures, and discovering necessary connections and impossibilities, without having any expertise in modern symbolic logic, and without using the Cartesian representation of geometry as a subset of arithmetic.
As far as I know, nobody has any idea what brain mechanisms make this possible and how they make it possible. E.g. how can a collection of neurons represent the fact that something is impossible, or necessarily true? How can a brain even represent the question whether something is impossible or necessarily true?
Most of the examples given above involved only straight and curved lines, points and lengths of portions of lines. Euclidean geometry also includes non-linearly extended structures, such as enclosed 2D regions and 3D volumes, as assumed by the question about a sphere rolling on a surface.
It also includes measures of lengths of straight or curved lines, measures of areas bounded by closed lines, and measures of volumes enclosed by surfaces. On a flat 2D surface a continuous closed boundary can be smooth, as in circle or ellipse, or with discontinuous changes of direction (i.e. corners), as in a triangle or square. Any mechanism explaining how human brains enable us to discover theorems in Euclidean geometry must explain how brains can represent and reason about all those shapes, and new shapes formed by combining them, and relationships between shapes.
Why do we not always need to have observed a huge variety of different examples with geometric properties in order to be able to derive consequences of those geometric properties by reasoning about them.
Many more examples are presented in Sloman(2015-18), and papers referred to there.
My impression is that apart from Piaget and a few others, hardly any researchers in psychology, neuroscience or AI have studied analyses of number competences by Hume, Frege, Russell and other philosophers of mathematics, and as a result most research in psychology or neuroscience of mathematics, or AI modelling of mathematical competences, shows no recognition of the fact that uses of cardinal and ordinal number concepts depend crucially on understanding properties of 1-1 correspondence, i.e. bijection, in particularly that it is necessarily transitive and symmetric -- i.e. exceptions are impossible. (Ordinal numbers are more complex, as explained below.)
There are some deceptive intermediate developmental states in which children and other animals show what looks like evidence of understanding cardinality in special situations, where in fact they merely use a different useful competence (e.g. template matching on small collections) that can be implemented in some brains without any general grasp of bijection.
Piaget understood this and his observations Piaget(1952) indicated that full (mathematical) understanding of bijection applied to physical objects does not develop until about the sixth year. (However all such claims are potentially subject to challenges based on new experimental setups that can reveal previously unnoticed earlier competences.)
A partial analysis of the roles of 1-1 correspondences in applications of number concepts, with some speculation about mechanisms required, was presented in Chapter 8 of Sloman 1978. (The online edition has additional notes and comments.)
As indicated there, such correspondences are independent of sensory modes (e.g. vision, hearing, touch) and can apply not only within a sensory mode (e.g. correspondence between two visible collections) but also across domains, e.g. vision and hearing, or vision and action (where objects are moved as they are counted), or counting beads on a string while blindfold. They also apply to bijections between static configurations and temporal patterns (e.g. counting).
For now the main point is that understanding cardinal numbers requires understanding that the relation of 1-1 correspondence between two sets of items is necessarily a transitive and symmetric relation. If this were not so, many of the practical applications of number concepts would not work, as discussed in Sloman(2016). How do you know that if there are 1-1 correspondences between sets A and B, and between sets B and C then there necessarily exists a 1-1 between sets A and C, no matter what sorts of entities are involved?
I suggest that understanding is based on recognition that 1-1 correspondences can be concatenated, as illustrated in the figure. I.e. 1-1 correspondence is transitive.
Moreover, that is not just an empirical generalisation: someone with "normal" school-level mathematical intuition should be able to understand that the possibility of concatenating two 1-1 correspondences with a common intermediate set of objects to form a new one, is independent of the particular numbers of set elements involved, the types of elements, where they are located in space, etc. Moreover, that insight requires a kind of "schematic" spatio-temporal understanding, not reasoning from definitions using logic. It is schematic, because the particular example can be understood to have features that are independent of the number of items involved.
The figure illustrates only one case, yet it appears that at least some human brains, though only after several years of development, as suggested by the findings in Piaget(1952), are able to understand that the transitivity cannot have exceptions: the basis of total reliance on transitivity in many different contexts.
All this can be understood even if A and C overlap, a point that is rarely noticed in discussions of numerical cognition. E.g. there can be 1-1 correspondences between a set of boys and a set of mugs, and between the set of mugs and the set of girls. And if there's a set of chairs in one-correspondence with the mugs, and some chairs are occupied by girls and some by boys, then both the set of boys and the set of girls is in 1-1 correspondence with the children on chairs, despite the overlaps.
For this reasons, diagrammatic explanations of numerical relationships can be misleading if no such overlaps are ever included. All this is second nature to mathematicians and most adults who are experts at counting and making uses of cardinality of sets. This is just one of many requirements that brains need to satisfy in order to support familiar but incompletely analysed competences, whose description in academic journals is often inaccurate. (I am also guilty of this.)
At what stage recognition of necessity/impossibility develops in individuals or in our evolution and what brain mechanisms and cultural support mechanisms are required are probably still unknown, although Piaget investigated some of the questions in his final two books (1981,1983). Unfortunately he lacked expertise in computational modelling, though he recognised the need shortly before his death. (In a speech at a conference in Geneva in 1980.)
As far as I know there is no known psychological or neural theory that identifies the mechanisms that support such recognition of necessary transitivity. For example Mareschal & Thomas(2006) don't even mention the requirement despite their focus on Piaget, who certainly understood it.
Nevertheless, this is an important feature of mathematical cognition, illustrating Kant's claim that arithmetical knowledge is synthetic, non-empirical, and necessary.
Understanding the use of numbers in continuous measures, e.g. distance, height, width, weight, etc. requires a much more sophisticated development, which may have occurred later in human history, though it builds on the evolutionary heritage underlying the uses of cardinals and ordinals, since measuring continuous quantities (e.g. length) using numerical values depends on one to one correspondences between locations (marks) on identical measuring rods, or other devices, e.g. human paces.
Deep learning mechanisms, using statistical evidence to derive probabilities are incapable of discovering, or representing, impossibility or necessity and therefore cannot acquire the kinds of knowledge described here. To that extent they are incapable of understanding the numerical concepts we, like ancient mathematicians, understand. However, it is no accident that arithmetical operations in computers give the same results as additions, subtractions, multiplication, etc. of the numbers discussed here.
That is because we have designed computers so that there is a mathematical (necessary) relationship between our arithmetic and bit-based computer arithmetic, although there are differences in speed and accuracy of execution. But a lot more has to be added to a computer system to enable it to make the discoveries made by ancient humans, such as that there are infinitely many natural numbers, and they include infinitely many prime numbers.
There is a rarely acknowledged complication regarding instances reappearing that is crucial to the difference between cardinals and ordinals. If the people who visit your office do so in the following order:
Andrew Basil Carol Andrew Daphne Edmund
Another complication allowed in ordinary parlance would be for two people to come at the same time, in which case they might both be third. Such complications could be crucial to unravelling a murder mystery, for example, but will not be pursued here.
A slightly different complication is allowed in many sporting events, which do not allow the same individual to occur in two positions in the results, but do allow two individuals to occupy the same position, with the proviso that the next position is empty. E.g. if Basil and Carol tied for second place, the results could be as followed, with nobody in third place:
1st: Andrew 2nd:{Basil, Carol} 3rd: 4th: Daphne 5th: Edmund
Yet more examples come from cyclic ordinals e.g. days of the week, months of the year, individuals sitting around a table.
These examples indicate that the concept of an ordinal structure, as used in everyday language and thought, is more complex than the concept of a cardinal.
That fact is not reflected in the mathematical theory of ordinals, as far as I am aware, since it does not allow duplicates, ties or cycles!
Testing your own understanding of 1-1 correspondence
Most mathematicians will very easily be able to answer this question, though non-mathematicians may have to think a little longer. Suppose there are two non-overlapping collections of objects C1 and C2. Is it possible for C1 to be in one-one correspondence with a proper subset of C2, while C2 is simultaneously in one-one correspondence with a proper subset of C1. If such correspondences both exist, what can you infer about C1?This is a simplified variant of a well known theorem that some readers will recognise (The Cantor-Schröder-Bernstein theorem). When I encountered the theorem as a student I decided to try to find the proof myself. I spent much time in the following days lying on my bed with my eyes shut, until I found the proof. So much for theories of mathematical cognition as embodied. Of course, it is embodied insofar as brains are required.
[Later I may add a note with more detail about the theorem and alternate proofs, using spatial or formal/logical reasoning.]
Video proof of pythagoras theorem:
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=0ZbB_-ip9VU
(please accept my apologies for referring to four triangles as four squares!).
For this diagrammatic proof to work do all the components have to be drawn with perfect precision? If not, how can we use imprecise diagrams and transformations to represent "perfect" Euclidean shapes and processes, as mathematicians have been doing for centuries, using drawings in sand, on slate, on paper, and various other other surfaces, and also imagined shapes, including imagined shapes indicated by a teacher pointing a bits of space, or tracing imaginary lines through space. All of these can play essential roles in mathematical discovery and mathematical communication.
How is that possible, given that similar techniques can't be used to prove
generalisations in physics, chemistry, geology, biology, etc.?
Or a more detailed presentation here by Eddie Woo:
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=tTHhBE5lYTg
Note the use of human abilities to perceive, manipulate and reason about spatial relationships, as opposed to logical or algebraic formulae.
In contrast, the demonstration based on allowing water to flow from two small
square containers to a larger square container, in the following video, does not
present a proof. Why not?
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=CAkMUdeB06o
Computer-based AI reasoners of that general sort are able to derive theorems in Euclidean geometry by constructing (and checking) proofs based on modern, logical, formulations of Euclid's axioms and postulates (e.g. Hilbert's or Tarski's axiomatisation), but they cannot replicate the original discovery processes based on mathematical intuition (using still unknown cognitive mechanisms in brains), that somehow enabled ancient mathematicians to discover Euclid's axioms, and centuries later Hilbert's and Tarski's axioms (among others).
If the Euclidean theorems are all stated in this form
If the axioms are all expressions in standard logical (e.g. predicate calculus)
notation, along with some abbreviative definitions, and the theorems are
provable using only logically valid inferences (whose validity depends only on
the logical forms used, not the contents referred to) then in a "modern"
interpretation of Kant's ideas, the consequents
Moreover there are geometrical discoveries that are not derivable from Euclidean
geometry, e.g. the neusis construction explained in
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/trisect.html
and Mary Pardoe's construction, described in
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/triangle-sum.html,
which supports a proof of the triangle sum theorem without reference to parallel
lines. I suggest that the brain mechanisms required for the
ancient mathematical discoveries
are related to Immanuel Kant's
claims about mathematical knowledge as being non-empirical, non-analytic and
non-contingent, alternatively expressed as a priori, synthetic and
necessary, as explained in
Sloman(1965).
Brain mechanisms required for those ancient discoveries are still
unknown. It may turn out that they depend essentially on the mixture of discrete
and continuous molecular processes inside synapses rather than being
explicable in terms of signals passing between neurons. Some half-baked
ideas about this are being explored elsewhere.
A very useful "short history" of the development of "infinitesimal calculus"
can be found on Wikipedia:
I shall later return to this paper and expand on the following claim: the
various mathematical discovery steps leading up to and including (for example)
the achievements of Leibniz and Newton, including the mathematical discoveries
and the uses of those discoveries in explaining and predicting physical
phenomena (e.g. astronomical observations, and tidal phenomena), could not be
replicated by any of the mechanisms developed in AI since it began in the work
of Turing and others, despite the fact that there have been computer programs,
designed by humans as opposed to being produced by machine learning systems,
that solve various subsets of those problems.
Whether some future advance in AI will falsify this claim is a separate
question, as is the question whether some fundamental new design for computers
that more closely represents mechanisms in brains (e.g. sub-neural chemical
mechanisms) will be required to support such discoveries.
-----WHEN I RETURN TO THIS PAPER I'LL REMOVE THESE TWO LINES--------
I think it is helpful to see Kant's philosophy of mathematics as an early
attempt, based on remarkably deep insights, to describe and explain some of the
most important features of ancient human mathematical discoveries and the
mechanisms that made those discoveries possible.
How can you know that you have checked all possibilities? The history of
mathematics shows that even brilliant mathematicians can make mistakes Lakatos (1976). This means that the traditional emphasis
on the role of "certainty" in mathematics may be misguided: certainty, or its
absence, like infallibility or its absence, is a matter of the psychology of
mathematicians, not the subject matter they investigate, which is something
richer and deeper: a feature of the universe that was playing a role in
evolution (the "Blind Mathematician") long before human mathematicians existed.
Computers, like drawings in sand, slates and chalk, pen and paper, 3-D models
made of wires and beads, and other aids to thinking and communication, have
expanded what human mathematicians can do, but not changed the nature of the
subject matter. Some are tempted to conclude that mathematics is essentially
a social phenomenon. That may be true for relatively weak mathematicians, though
there are others who do their main work struggling with problems, not talking to
colleagues.
Nowadays the role of colleagues is increasingly being supplemented
by various roles of computers in supporting mathematical research, some
discussed in Wolfram(2007).
However, Kant's ideas about the nature of mathematical discovery, and roles for
mathematical insight or intuition in making discoveries, remain relevant to many
human mathematical discoveries, even if there is increasing use of computers to
aid mathematical research, including use of logic.
Jordana Cepelewicz, 2016
How Does a Mathematician's Brain Differ from That of a Mere Mortal?
Scientific American Online April 12, 2016
Jackie Chappell and Aaron Sloman (2007a). Natural and artificial meta-configured
altricial information-processing systems. (2007a)
International Journal of Unconventional Computing, 3(3), 211-239.
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/07.html#717
Jackie Chappell and Aaron Sloman, (2007b)
Two ways of understanding causation: Humean and Kantian,
M.B. Clowes,
1973,
Man the creative machine: A perspective from Artificial Intelligence research,
in The Limits of Human Nature,
Ed. J. Benthall,
Allen Lane, London.
Chris Christensen (2013)
Review of Biographies of Alan Turing, Cryptologia,
37:4, 356-367,
Kenneth Craik, 1943,
The Nature of Explanation,
Cambridge University Press, London, New York
David Deutsch, 1997
The Fabric of Reality,
David Deutsch, 2011
The Beginning of Infinity: Explanations That Transform the World,
Euclid and John Casey (2007)
The First Six Books of the Elements of Euclid,
Project Gutenberg, Salt Lake City,
Third Edition, Revised and enlarged.
Dublin: Hodges, Figgis, \& Co., Grafton-St.
London: Longmans, Green, \& Co. 1885,
H. Gelernter, 1964,
Realization of a geometry-theorem proving machine,
reprinted in
Computers and Thought,
Eds. Edward A. Feigenbaum and Julian Feldman,
McGraw-Hill,
New York,
pp. 134-152,
Robert Geretschlager, 1995.
Euclidean Constructions and the Geometry of Origami,
Mathematics Magazine, 68, 5, pp. 357--371,
Mathematical Association of America,
http://www.jstor.org/stable/2690924
James J. Gibson, 1979
The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception,
Houghton Mifflin,
Boston, MA,
Ira Goldstein, 1973,
Elementary Geometry Theorem Proving
MIT AI Memo 280, April 1973
Yacin Hamami and John Mumma, 2013,
Prolegomena to a Cognitive Investigation of Euclidean Diagrammatic Reasoning, in
Journ Log Lang Inf 22, pp 421-448
Carl G. Hempel,
Geometry and Empirical Science, 1945,
American Mathematical Monthly, Vol 52,
Reprinted in
Readings in Philosophical Analysis, eds. H. Feigl and W. Sellars,
New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1949,
David Hilbert, 1899,
The Foundations of Geometry,, available at
Project Gutenberg,
Salt Lake City,
http://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/17384
2005,
Translated 1902 by E.J. Townsend, from 1899 German edition,
Andrew Hodges, 1999. Turing. New York: Routledge.
T. Ida and J. Fleuriot, Eds.,
Proc. 9th Int. Workshop on Automated Deduction in Geometry (ADG 2012),
Edinburgh,
September,
2012,
University of Edinburgh,
Informatics Research Report,
Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (1781)
Imre Lakatos, Proofs and Refutations,
John McCarthy and Patrick J. Hayes, 1969,
"Some philosophical problems from the standpoint of AI",
Machine Intelligence 4,
Eds. B. Meltzer and D. Michie,
pp. 463--502,
Edinburgh University Press,
Kenneth Manders (1998)
The Euclidean Diagram, reprinted 2008 in
The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice, OUP, pp.80--133
Ed Paolo Mancosu,
Kenneth Manders (2008)
"Diagram-Based Geometric Practice",
In Paolo Mancosu (ed.),
The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. OUP, pp.65--79
D. Mareschal and M. S. C. Thomas, "How computational models help explain the
origins of reasoning," in
IEEE Computational Intelligence Magazine, vol. 1, no.
3, pp. 32-40, Aug. 2006.
doi: 10.1109/MCI.2006.1672986
Noboru Matsuda and Kurt Vanlehn (2004),
GRAMY: A Geometry Theorem Prover Capable of Construction,
Journal of Automated Reasoning
Vol 32 (3--33)
Kluwer Academic Publishers. Netherlands.
David Mumford, 2016,
Grammar isn't merely part of language,
Online Blog,
Tuck Newport,
Brains and Computers: Amino Acids versus Transistors,
Jean Piaget, (1952). The Child's Conception of Number.
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Piaget, 1981, 1983
Jean Piaget's last two (closely related) books written with collaborators are
relevant, though I don't think he had good explanatory theories.
(Like Kant, Piaget had deep observations but lacked an understanding of
information processing mechanisms, required for explanatory theories.)
Gualtiero Piccinini (2003),
Alan Turing and the Mathematical Objection,
Minds and Machines
L. J. Rips, A. Bloomfield and J. Asmuth,
2008,
From Numerical Concepts to Concepts of Number,
The Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
Vol 31, no 6, pp. 623--642,
Carl J. Posy (Ed), 1992
Kant's Philosophy of Mathematics-Modern Essays
Synthese Library Vol 219
Kluwer Academic Publishers
Erwin Schrödinger (1944)
What is life? CUP, Cambridge,
Dana Scott, 2014,
Geometry without points.
(Video lecture,
23 June 2014,University of Edinburgh)
Frege on the Foundation of Geometry in Intuition
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy
Vol 3, No 6. pp 1-23,
Siemann, J., & Petermann, F.
(2018).
Innate or Acquired? - Disentangling Number Sense and Early Number Competencies.
Frontiers in psychology,
9, 571.
doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2018.00571
Sloman, A. (1962). Knowing and Understanding: Relations between meaning and
truth, meaning and necessary truth, meaning and synthetic necessary truth
(DPhil Thesis),
Oxford University. (Transcribed version online.)
Aaron Sloman (1963/5)
Functions and Rogators,
In Formal Systems and Recursive Functions:
Proceedings of the Eighth Logic Colloquium Oxford, July 1963,
Eds. J. N. Crossley and M. A. E. Dummett,
North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1965, pp. 156--175.
Aaron Sloman, 1965,
"Necessary", "A Priori" and "Analytic",
Analysis, Vol 26, No 1, pp. 12--16.
A. Sloman, 1971, "Interactions between philosophy and AI: The role of
intuition and non-logical reasoning in intelligence", in
Proc 2nd IJCAI,
pp. 209--226, London. William Kaufmann. Reprinted in
Artificial Intelligence,
vol 2, 3-4, pp 209-225, 1971.
A. Sloman, 1978
The Computer Revolution in Philosophy,
A. Sloman, (1978b). What About Their Internal Languages? Commentary on three articles by
Premack, D., Woodruff, G., by Griffin, D.R., and by Savage-Rumbaugh, E.S., Rumbaugh,
D.R., Boysen, S. in BBS Journal 1978, 1 (4).
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1(4), 515.
Aaron Sloman (2012-...),
The Meta-Morphogenesis (Self-Informing Universe) Project
(begun 2012, with several progress reports, but still work in progress).
"Some (possibly) new considerations regarding impossible objects" Aaron Sloman,
2015, ff.). (Including their significance for (a) mathematical cognition, (b)
serious limitations of current AI vision systems, and (c) philosophy of mind,
i.e. possible contents of consciousness).
Aaron Sloman, 2013--2018,
Jane Austen's concept of information (Not Claude Shannon's)
Aaron Sloman, 2016,
Natural Vision and Mathematics: Seeing Impossibilities, in
Proceedings of Second Workshop on: Bridging the Gap between Human and Automated
Reasoning,
IJCAI 2016, pp.86--101, Eds. Ulrich Furbach and Claudia Schon,
July, 9, New York,
A. Sloman (with help from Jackie Chappell), 2017-8,
The Meta-Configured Genome (unpublished)
A. Sloman, 2018a,
A Super-Turing (Multi) Membrane Machine for Geometers Part 1
A. Sloman, 2018b
A Super-Turing (Multi) Membrane Machine for Geometers Part 2
Aaron Sloman, 2018c,
Wikipedia contributors,
Tarski's axioms for geometry
Wikipedia, The Free Encyclopedia,
Trettenbrein, Patrick C., 2016,
The Demise of the Synapse As the Locus of Memory: A Looming Paradigm Shift?,
Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience,
Vol 88,
A. M. Turing, (1950) Computing machinery and intelligence,
A. M. Turing, (1952),
'The Chemical Basis Of Morphogenesis', in
John von Neumann, 1958
The Computer and the Brain
(Silliman Memorial Lectures),
Yale University Press. 3rd Edition, with Foreword by Ray Kurzweill. Originally published 1958.
Wikipedia contributors, 2018,
Mathematics of paper folding
Wikipedia, The Free Encyclopedia,
Alastair Wilson, 2017,
Metaphysical Causation,
Nous
Stephen Wolfram (2007),
Mathematics, Mathematica and Certainty
Wolfram Blog December 8, 2007
Maintained by
Aaron Sloman
IF
where
Discovery/invention of differential/integral calculus an example?
This section is mainly for readers who are already acquainted with differential
and integral calculus, at least at a fairly low undergraduate level, with
personal experience of solving typical student problems (finding derivatives or
integrals).
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/History_of_calculus
A possibly useful supplement that I have not yet examined closely is
https://medium.com/explore-artificial-intelligence/the-birth-of-calculus-8e14e01f4550
-----ITEMS BELOW ARE PLACE-HOLDERS FOR SECTIONS TO BE ADDED------
Evolution's use of compositionality (and Kant)
The term "compositionality" is most often used to refer to features of language
involving at least two types of structure with systematic relationships between
them, in particular:
-- syntactic (grammatical) structures of phrases, sentences, paragraphs, etc.
-- semantic structures expressed or denoted by those linguistic items
However it is useful/illuminating to point out that in a generalised sense
"compositionality" is a feature of many aspects of biological evolution and its
products, including its information processing mechanisms.
For more details see Sloman(2018c), which
explains, among other things, how the uses of compositionality in evolution, and
in individual development as genomes are expressed, can involve mathematical
structures and processes.
Did Lakatos refute Kant?
One of the fundamental requirements for mathematical thinking is being able to
organise collections of possibilities and making sure that you have checked them
all. If you can't do that you don't have a mathematical result, only a guess.
Some themes to be added
Work is in progress on a theory relating processs of biological evolution
and mechanisms by which information acquired during evolution can be used in
descendents of the first users,
REFERENCES AND LINKS
H.G. Barrow and J.M. Tenenbaum, 1981,
Interpreting Line Drawings as Three-Dimensional Surfaces, in
Artificial Intelligence, 17, pp. 75--116,
(Draft list: to be pruned, etc. later.)
http://web.mit.edu/cocosci/Papers/Barrow-Tenenbaum81.pdf
https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/how-does-a-mathematician-s-brain-differ-from-that-of-a-mere-mortal/
Contributions to WONAC: International Workshop on Natural and Artificial Cognition
Pembroke College, Oxford,
June 25-26,
2007,
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/talks/wonac
https://doi.org/10.1080/01611194.2013.827532
Craik drew attention to previously unnoticed problems about biological
information processing in intelligent animals.
For a draft incomplete discussion of his contribution, see
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/kenneth-craik.html
Allen Lane and Penguin Books
Allen Lane and Penguin Books, London.
http://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/21076
http://dl.acm.org/citation.cfm?id=216408.216418
https://dspace.mit.edu/handle/1721.1/5798
http://doi.org/10.1007/s10849-013-9182-8
http://www.ditext.com/hempel/geo.html
http://dream.inf.ed.ac.uk/events/adg2012/uploads/proceedings/ADG2012-proceedings.pdf
has relevant ideas and questions, but he lacked our present understanding of
information processing (which is still too limited)
http://archive.org/details/immanuelkantscri032379mbp
Cambridge University Press, 1976,
http://www-formal.stanford.edu/jmc/mcchay69/mcchay69.html
http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199296453.003.0005
http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199296453.003.0004
http://ieeexplore.ieee.org/stamp/stamp.jsp?tp=&arnumber=1672986&isnumber=35104
http://www.public.asu.edu/~kvanlehn/Stringent/PDF/04JAR_NM_KVL.pdf
http://www.dam.brown.edu/people/mumford/blog/2016/grammar.html
2015,
Kindle,
Discusses implications of href="#von-Neumann-brain">von Neumann 1958,
https://www.amazon.com/dp/B00OQFN6LA
Vol 1. The role of possibility in cognitive development (1981)
Vol 2. The role of necessity in cognitive development (1983)
University of Minnesota Press, Tr. by Helga Feider from French in 1987
Feb, 2003,
Kluwer Academic
http://dx.doi.org/10.1023/A:1021348629167
https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X08005566
I have an annotated version of part of this book here (also PDF):
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/schrodinger-life.html
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=sDGnE8eja5o
https://jhaponline.org/jhap/issue/view/271
https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/29725316
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/62-80.html#1962
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/07.html#714
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/62-80.html#1965-02
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/cogaff/62-80.html#1971-02
A slightly expanded
version was published as chapter 7 of Sloman 1978,
available here.
Harvester Press (and Humanities Press), Hassocks, Sussex.
Free, partly revised, edition online:
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/cogaff/62-80.html#crp
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/62-80.html#1978-02
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/meta-morphogenesis.html
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/meta-morphogenesis.pdf
The web page is based on a set of notes and examples prepared for an invited
talk on vision at Bristol University, on 2nd Oct 2015, substantially extended at
various times since then:
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/impossible.html
Online technical report, University of Birmingham,
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/austen-info.html
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/austen-info.pdf
http://ceur-ws.org/Vol-1651/
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/sloman-bridging-gap-2016.pdf
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/meta-configured-genome.html
(Also for toddlers, and other intelligent animals)
PART 1: Philosophical and biological background
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/super-turing-phil.html
(Also for toddlers, and other intelligent animals)
PART 2: Towards a specification for mechanisms
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/super-turing-geom.html
Biologically Evolved Forms of Compositionality
Structural relations and constraints
vs Statistical correlations and probabilities
http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/research/projects/cogaff/misc/compositionality.html
(also PDF).
Expanded version of paper accepted for First Symposium on Compositional
Structures (SYCO 1)
Sept 2018 School of Computer Science, University of Birmingham, UK
http://events.cs.bham.ac.uk/syco/1/
[Accessed 6-November-2018]
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Tarski%27s_axioms
http://doi.org/10.3389/fnsys.2016.00088
Mind, 59, pp. 433--460, 1950,
(reprinted in many collections, e.g. E.A. Feigenbaum and J. Feldman (eds)
Computers and Thought McGraw-Hill, New York, 1963, 11--35),
WARNING: some of the online and published copies of this paper have errors,
including claiming that computers will have 109 rather than 109 bits
of memory. Anyone who blindly copies that error cannot be trusted as a commentator.
Phil. Trans. R. Soc. London B 237, 237, pp. 37--72.
(Also reprinted(with commentaries) in
S. B. Cooper and J. van Leeuwen, EDs (2013)).
A useful summary of Turing's 1952 paper for non-mathematicians is:
Philip Ball, 2015,
Forging patterns and making waves from biology to geology:
a commentary on Turing (1952) `The chemical basis of morphogenesis',
Royal Society Philosophical Transactions B,
http://dx.doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2014.0218
https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Mathematics_of_paper_folding&oldid=862366869
https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12190
http://blog.wolfram.com/2007/12/08/mathematics-mathematica-and-certainty/
Updates
Originally installed: 11 Dec 2018
Based on a different paper installed early October 2018.
This work, and everything else on my website, is licensed under a
Creative
Commons Attribution 4.0 License.
If you use or comment on my ideas please include a URL if possible, so
that readers can see the original, or the latest version.
Creative Commons License
School of Computer Science
The University of Birmingham